Democritus, the next of the pre-Socratic philosophers in our History of Philosophy Refracted through Perfume series criticized Anaxagoras' explanation of qualities. Anaxagoras had hypothesized that the bits corresponding to the salient qualities of a thing are present in greater proportion than are the bits of other things. A bottle of Tom Ford Black Orchid contains a liquid which smells like Black Orchid because it is made up of many tiny little “Black Orchid” bits. His reasoning, to review, was in effect:
How could Black Orchid come from what is not Black Orchid, or Allure from what is not Allure?
The
atoms—as Democritus and his mentor, Leucippus, did in fact refer to
them—making up a perfume bottle are not tiny perfume bottles, or
even pieces of glass. Nor does the liquid inside comprise individual
“bits” sharing the qualities of the whole. Instead, the atoms are
altogether devoid of such sensorily perceivable qualities. We do not
perceive anything at all until the atoms have coalesced into much
larger congeries. Out of nothing, something comes. Where there were
no observable properties, suddenly they pop into our view, becoming a
part of our reality because they are experienced by us.
The
atoms have extension and shape, but they possess no qualities
perceivable by human beings through their sense organs alone. It is
only when the atoms are brought together in certain combinations and
proportions that such qualities arise, emergently, out of the
arrangements of individual atoms. Between the atoms is space.
Sound familiar? Yes, Leucippus and Democritus did indeed anticipate modern theories of chemistry, according to which all objects, including perfumes, comprise molecules, and all molecules are built up of atoms. Chemistry has obviously been refined over the more than 2,000 years since these pre-Socratic thinkers amazingly hit on something like it by casting about in an aim to understand the world in which they found themselves. We now identify the atoms in question as Carbon, Hydrogen, Oxygen, etc. The early atomists knew nothing about the scientifically hypothesized atoms of the nineteenth and twentieth century. Was it just a lucky guess, a stab in the dark? My hunch is that their bold conjectures were based on their first-hand experience of perfume.
Sound familiar? Yes, Leucippus and Democritus did indeed anticipate modern theories of chemistry, according to which all objects, including perfumes, comprise molecules, and all molecules are built up of atoms. Chemistry has obviously been refined over the more than 2,000 years since these pre-Socratic thinkers amazingly hit on something like it by casting about in an aim to understand the world in which they found themselves. We now identify the atoms in question as Carbon, Hydrogen, Oxygen, etc. The early atomists knew nothing about the scientifically hypothesized atoms of the nineteenth and twentieth century. Was it just a lucky guess, a stab in the dark? My hunch is that their bold conjectures were based on their first-hand experience of perfume.
Perfumes which look empirically indistinguishable often smell wildly different. How to explain this disparity in perception? The problem with Anaxagoras' theory was that all things were said to be made up of things which they resemble. This does not help in explaining the distinction in smell between two liquids of the same color.
Take some perfumes by Annick Goutal with similar shades of color, say Quel Amour, Eau d'Hadrien, and Petite Chérie. These perfumes smell radically different. What makes these perfumes distinct, despite their visual similarities, is not that they comprise tiny bits of, respectively, Quel Amour, Eau d'Hadrien, and Petite Chérie.
Why, again, do beautiful, fully composed perfumes comprising high-quality materials, such as Miller Harris Jasmin Vert or Géranium Bourbon or Figue Amère smell so different from a vat-produced chemical soup which induces dread and malaise in the wearer? (The selection of examples is left as an exercise for the reader.) It is not because the former are made up of tiny homuncular (so to speak) bottles of great perfume. No, something else must be going on, the atomists correctly inferred.
True,
one can dig deeper, if one wishes, but theories of multidimensional
strings are not going to provide much insight in attempting to
understand why when an ebay hawk or grey market decanter dilutes a
perfume it smells weaker than it did before. We modern people pretty
much call it a day at the level of chemistry, which helpfully
explains all sorts of empirical phenomena readily observable by us.
Colligative
properties such as freezing point depression and boiling point
elevation are good examples. Why does making a sorbet with a touch of
alcohol added yield a softer outcome than a sorbet mixture to which
no alcohol is added? Why does pouring salt on the sidewalk in
wintertime prevent ice from forming?
We can even understand in the basic concepts of organic chemistry why trans-fats are worse than cis-fats. Chemistry offers satisfying answers to these questions. Digging deeper is possible, and physicists certainly do that when they go to work in their laboratories, but good luck trying to grapple with aspects of everyday existence—becoming—through appeal to strings. You may as well just return with Parmenides to the realm of Being!
Where there was no Jean Patou 1000, suddenly it appeared, in a grand creation act, as though plucked from a magician's hat, when an assortment of atoms (in molecules) were juxtaposed in just the right way and in the right proportions. That's pretty much all that we need to know, and all that perfumers need to know as they scrupulously document their new formulas so that it will be possible in the future, to reproduce over and over again—should anyone choose to do so—the final combination of ingredients which make up what has been christened a new perfume.
Democritus
was a materialist interested in mechanical explanations of phenomena.
He was a “How?” man, not a “Why?” man. For this reason, some
historians have considered him to be more of a protoscientist than a
philosopher. In fact, his predilection for mechanical explanations
was itself a philosophical position, in some ways anticipatory of
modern pragmatism. What works is valid, and what does not work is
invalid. That is the essence of pragmatism, in a nutshell. And it
rings true for perfume as well.
An
iconic perfume has succeeded in carving out a new spot of previously
uncharted territory on the grand olfactory map. A second requirement,
for even a highly original perfume to achieve true icon status, is
that it enjoy widespread market success. Many perfumes carve out new
spots of previously uncharted territory, but for one reason or
another they are market flops. Usually they are discontinued. Only
iconic perfumes hit on a formula which appeals to a sufficient number
of consumers to warrant keeping the perfume in production. But the
contribution of the house, its willingness and ability to market the
perfume is even more important to contemporary recognition than is
the nature of the creation itself. The Britney Spears perfume collection has reaped millions upon millions of dollars of profits.
Curious, Fantasy, In Control Curious, Midnight Fantasy,
Believe, Curious Heart, Hidden Fantasy, Circus Fantasy
(Not Pictured: Radiance and Cosmic Radiance)
|
Materialism
and Hedonism
The
retention of the same name for what has become a different perfume,
as in the case of Guerlain Mitsouko,
or the preposterous renaming of Miss
Dior Chérie
as Miss
Dior,
may on its face
appear to provide confirmation of the Parmenidean view on the realm
of becoming, that it is the realm of falsehood and illusion. Then
again, Yves Saint Laurent Champagne
was also renamed, to Yvresse,
not because of a blunder on the part of some officious executive
wishing to leave his grimy fingerprints on the perfume, but because
of a testy dispute with French champagne makers over what they took
to be the inappropriate use of that term.
Everything is fair game in the realm of becoming, and people will do what they will do in order to get what they want. But if all acts of naming are a matter of convention, then is anyone really to blame for retaining the name of a formerly great perfume and using it to label a less noble variant of the same? Whatever works, works. What does not work, does not work. We find ourselves, my fragrant friends, yet again, in the realm of Parmenidean tautology, now in the service of an eminently non-Parmenidean philosophy!
Everything is fair game in the realm of becoming, and people will do what they will do in order to get what they want. But if all acts of naming are a matter of convention, then is anyone really to blame for retaining the name of a formerly great perfume and using it to label a less noble variant of the same? Whatever works, works. What does not work, does not work. We find ourselves, my fragrant friends, yet again, in the realm of Parmenidean tautology, now in the service of an eminently non-Parmenidean philosophy!
In
a materialist world view such as that of Democritus and the atomists,
everything, including morality, is a matter of convention. There is
no higher power; there are no laws written in invisible ink in the
sky; and there is no afterlife—whether filled with heavenly bliss
or eternal damnation. What you see—or sniff—here and now, on
planet earth, is what you get.
In
this sort of world view, materialistic hedonism, there is no pure and
absolute, immutable essence or Platonic Form of Perfume (to
anticipate a bit future episodes of this lengthy story...). No,
perfumes are short-lived, fragile creations, creatures of sorts, kept
in existence only for so long as they prove to be profitable to
someone somewhere. It's not enough that a perfume once launched be loved; it must
also earn its right to continue to exist.
Once
a perfume has ceased pulling its weight, so to speak, perfume houses
simply pull the plug. From the hard-headed perspective of
pragmatically oriented materialists, vain attempts to re-create the perfumes of centuries past are futile efforts to change the structure
of reality as conceived by naturalistically minded thinkers such as
the atomists of ancient Greece.
One
interesting implication of a hedonistic picture of perfume
appreciation—such as seems clearly to be implied by the atomism
championed first by Leucippus and Democritus, and later by Epicurus
(who, too, will be discussed in more detail in a future
episode...)—may be that many perfumistas, in their enthusiasm to
exalt perfumery as an art, give short shrift to the impact of
marketing on our reception of perfume.
This picture lends weight to the idea, discussed in The Bottle Controversy, that the vessel in which a perfume is housed and travels and from which perfume is drawn, being a sensorily perceived object, is no less worthy of our attention because it is no less capable of producing pleasurable sensations in us. The question becomes: in terms of the overall pleasure derived, is the bottle less important than the scent inside? While it is true that the bottle can lead one deceptively to buy a perfume which does not deliver on the promise of its packaging, the same can be said of advertising more generally. In fact, that is what advertising is: seduction, pure and simple. Do you really need that item or gadget—or bottle? Advertising has as its aim to convince you that you do.
There is a substantive sense in which the bottle contributes to the overall success of a marketing campaign. But there is a difference: the bottle is an independent object, designed by someone somewhere no less than was the perfume, and therefore potentially worthy of our regard. It, too, exists to our sensory organs because a group of atoms and molecules have been brought together and arranged in a particular way so as to affect our sensory receptors. When the sight or touch of a bottle provides pleasure, then it has just as much value as any other source of pleasure, including the scent of perfume.
That, at any rate, my fellow fragrant travelers, is the way in which the ancient Greek pre-Socratic philosopher Democritus appears to have viewed these matters.